A change of heart? 1
Physics and mathematics: 2
What is a noncommuting operator?
Is the historicity of pi ineluctable?
Complex number theory
Weinberg criticizes Latour for agreeing with him.
When is a boundary not a boundary?
Reality: 6
On a wing and a prayer
Werner's wanderings.
To put it simply
Weinberg reads Harding.
Lynch corrects Weinberg.
Clues to the past.
Rationality and witchcraft.
In Reading and relativism, I said that, on a normal reading, Steven Weinbergs, Sokals hoax, (New York Review, August 8, 1996) is clear and convincing but, on a skeptical one, it can be seen to be riddled with confusion. I also gave three examples of this phenomenon.2 Here I offer moremore than enough, I believe, to justify my use of the term riddled.
After Sokal exposed his hoax, one of the editors of Social Text even speculated that Sokals parody was nothing of the sort, and that his admission represented a change of heart, or a folding of his intellectual resolve. I am reminded of the case of the American spiritualist Margaret Fox. When she confessed in 1888 that her career of seances and spirit rappings had all been a hoax, other spiritualists claimed that it was her confession that was dishonest.
Weinberg is quoting here from the Social Text editors reply to Sokals announcement of his hoax. 3 However, because the editors do not mention how long the alleged speculation was entertained, he has no warrant to assume, as he implicitly does by his allusion to followers of Margaret Fox, that it was long enough to justify mocking the editor for having entertained it. For all he knows, it was merely an initial, perhaps even momentary, reaction to news of Sokals disturbing claim. Weinberg also shows no curiosity about why the editors of Social Text would appear to volunteer information that he considers damning at the beginning of an article devoted to defending themselves against Sokals attack. Isnt this a reason for him to pause and consider carefully whether his take on what they are saying is accurate? Finally, if, as I strongly suspect, Weinberg grants that people do sometimes recant their views under pressure, 4 then he owes us an explanation of why it would have been unreasonable for the editor, upon hearing of Sokals claim but not yet knowing any of the particulars, to consider the possibility that it was a case of this kind.
In his description of Sokals parody, Weinberg mentions alleged howlers about physics and mathematics that were committed either intentionally by Sokal or unwittingly by others in statements that Sokal quoted and pretended to admire.5 Below I consider three of the first kind and two of the second.
What is a noncommuting operator? In the following passage, Weinberg pays a price for failing to meticulously distinguish between singular and plural. It leads him to see a physics blooper that isnt there and miss one that is.
In arguing for the cultural importance of the quantum theory of gravitation, Sokal refers to the gravitational field in this theory as a noncommuting (and hence nonlinear) operator. Here hence is ridiculous; noncommuting does not imply nonlinear, and in fact quantum mechanics deals with things that are both noncommuting and linear.
The term linear applies to an individual operator but noncommuting applies only to a set of two or more of them. Weinbergs seemingly innocuous use of the word things blurs the distinction between singular and plural in a way that causes him both to talk nonsense and fail to notice the blooper that is present in Sokals remark. Contrary to what he says, it is not hence but the expression, a noncommuting operator. Because there is no such thing as a noncommuting operator.
Is the historicity of pi ineluctable? A little later, he writes:
Sokal solemnly pronounces that the pi of Euclid and the G of Newton, formerly thought to be constant and universal, are now perceived in their ineluctable historicity. This is absurdthe meaning of a mathematical quantity like pi cannot be affected by discoveries in physics, and in any case both pi and G continue to appear as universal constants in the equations of general relativity.
The meaning of a mathematical quantity? Mathematical quantities no more have meanings than do chairs or potatoes.6 Maybe Weinberg meant to say nature not meaning. I will assume that he did but this does not explain why he talks about discoveries in physics. There is nothing in Sokals statement about discoveries in physics. In it, he pretends to talk of an alleged change in our perception of pi and G but he says nothing about how it came about. Does the fact that pi and G continue to appear in equations as universal constants necessarily conflict with their being perceived in their ineluctable historicity? I dont see why, if only because this is so vague. Weinberg was quick to dismiss Derridas the Einsteinian constant is not a constant, not a center as jibber jabber. Yet he is unfazed by the pi of Euclid and the G of Newton are now perceived in their ineluctable historicity. He finds it false and ridiculous but not meaningless or even ambiguous.
But how can he discern a unique meaning here?7 In my dictionary, to perceive something in its ineluctable historicity is to perceive it in its unavoidable historical actuality, which is vague enough to allow for different readings of Sokals sentence, none of them especially compelling. For example, it might entail recognizing that each culture has to decide anew what if anything mathematics is about. Recall that on a Platonist conception of mathematics, pi and everything else is a set, whereas on a constructivist one, it is a rule.8 For those who take their ontology seriously, these are very different things. (See, for example, Realistic Rationalism by the analytic philosopher, Jerrold Katz.) True, Sokals sentence begins as if it is going to say that our belief in the constancy of pi is mistaken. But, perhaps out of fear that the editors might wake up or because he found the word ineluctable ineluctable, Sokal opted instead for postmodernist obfuscation. How then can Weinberg presume to understand the sentence well enough to fault the editors of Social Text for not reading it the way he does? Did he even look for a different reading?
Addendum: Perhaps because Weinberg knew that he was reading a parody, when he saw the absurdity to which the first part of the sentence seemed to be heading, it was natural for him to treat it as the meaning of the otherwise obscure second part. But the editors didnt know they were reading a parody. They believed they were considering a submission by a professor of physics at New York University, written in a self-consciously postmodernist style that they had reluctantly agreed to tolerate, containing nothing that he would not say to his own colleagues.9 In these circumstances, the editors should not have read Sokals sentence the way Weinberg felt free to read it. On the contrary, charity required that the reading on which it terminates in postmodernist obfuscation trump the one on which a professor of physics at a reputable university is saying something idiotic about high school science or mathematics.10
Complex number theory? A little later, Weinberg says, about one of Sokals footnotes:
[Sokal] refers to complex number theory as a new and still quite speculative branch of mathematical physics, while in fact it is nineteenth century mathematics and as well established as anything ever gets.
Contrary to this assertion, the expression complex number theory does not name any nineteenth century or, for that matter, any other kind of mathematics. That Weinberg thinks it does shows that he is not a mathematician.12 For the area of mathematics that he has in mind, mathematicians have several different names. The closest to complex number theory is complex function theory.13 But saying that complex function theory is a new and still quite speculative branch of mathematical physics was not an option for Sokal. Although Weinberg does not seem to have realized it, Sokal was mimicking Robert Markley. In a statement quoted in the parody, Markley has complex number theory where the context seems to call for either complex systems theory or complexity theory, both of which do name a new and still quite speculative branch of mathematical physics. None of this seems to have registered with Weinberg.
In the next two examples, Weinberg considers physics and mathematics bloopers in remarks of others that Sokal quotes with sly mock approval.13
Weinberg criticizes Latour for agreeing with him. In Reading and relativism, I pointed out two misreadings by Sokal of an essay by Bruno Latour about a popular book by Einstein. The book is an informal account of relativity theory for a lay reader. Here is a similar misreading by by Weinberg of a passage from the same essay by Latour.
How can one decide whether an observation made in a train about the behavior of a falling stone can be made to coincide with the observation of the same falling stone from the embankment? If there are only one, or even two, frames of reference, no solution can be found Einsteins solution is to consider three actors (Latour, as quoted by Sokal)
This is wrong: in relativity theory there is no difficulty in comparing the results of two, three, or any number of observers. (Weinberg)
According to Weinberg, Latour is mistaken in saying that, in relativity theory, there is a difficulty in comparing observations made in different frames of reference. But Latour does not say that, in relativity theory, no solution can be found. On the contrary, relativity theory provides the solution.14 It tells us how to compare observations made in different frames. What then is Latours point? On my reading, he simply is noting that the frames alone are not enough. In a passage that Weinberg omits, he explains:
If there are only one, or even two, frames of reference, no solution can be found since the man in the train claims he observes a straight line and the man on the embankment a parabola. Thus nothing tells us if it is the same stone acting according to the same law of physics. Each observer has its own irreducible vision of the world.
This is the sense in which the frames of reference are not enough. We also need the right transformations from each of them to a common frame. Relativity theory tells us that these are the Lorentz transformations. Thus, Latour and Weinberg agree that, in relativity theory, there is no difficulty in making such comparisons.
But if so, what is this third actor? Physicists never talk about a third actor. Well, on my reading, Latours observers can make observations (and maybe even transmit data) but it is not necessarily part of their job description to make comparisons. The third actor is a person or device that can use the Lorentz transformations to do this. But it needs a frame into which data received from the two observers is translated. Must this frame be different from the first two? No, nor does Latour ever suggest such a thing. On the contrary, elsewhere in his essay, he emphasizes that there are no privileged frames. In principle, any frame will do. In particular, either of the first two frames can be used.15 Latour takes explicit note of this in his essay.
If the man in the train describes scenes according to instruments, which, after a few transformations, are made equivalent to the ones seen by the man on the embankment, this means that the latter will gain something. Without being on the train, the man on the embankment will have its point of view plus another one compatible and addable to the first.16
When is a boundary not a boundary? Sokals article includes the following quotation from a work by Luce Irigaray.
The mathematical sciences, in the theory of sets, concern themselves with closed and open spaces They concern themselves very little with the question of the partially open, with sets that are not clearly delineated [ensembles flous], with any analysis of the problem of borders [bords] 17 (Irigaray)
According to Weinberg, this merely reveals Irigarays ignorance. Focusing on her last comment, he writes:
Luce Irigaray deplores mathematicians neglect of spaces with boundaries, though there is a huge literature on the subject. (Weinberg)
As a reply to Irigaray, this is risible. There is indeed an immense literature of the kind that Weinberg mentions but little if any of it promises to be of any use in studying the problem of borders for sets that are not clearly delineated, i.e., for fuzzy sets or vague predicates. What do the boundaries of algebraic, differential or point-set topology have to do with boundaries of vague predicates, e.g., color names? It seems that Weinberg has failed to grasp the relevance of Irigarays mention of fuzzy sets for understanding what kind of borders she is most reasonably taken to be talking about.18 Indeed, it is precisely the fuzziness of a fuzzy setthe vagueness of a vague predicatethat makes its border problematic.
On my reading, throughout this essay, Weinberg is speaking in opposition to the idea, which he thinks he sees expressed in the writings of others, that what we call scientific knowledge is no better than any other belief. I think he is seriously confused about this and that many of the particular confusions I point out below are reflections of this general one. But I will not try to argue the general point here.
On a wing and a prayer
I have come to think that the laws of physics are real because my experience with the laws of physics does not seem to me to be very different in any fundamental way from my experience with rocks. For those who have not lived with the laws of physics, I can offer the obvious argument that the laws of physics as we know them work, and there is no other known way of looking at nature that works in anything like the same sense.
If one believes that a statement is a law of physics, what does it add to say that it is real? To put it another way, what is the difference between saying I believe the law of the lever and I think that the law of the lever is real? I dont see any, except that the second statement is not a normal way of talking. So, on one reading, Weinberg is merely saying, albeit in a queer way, that he believes the laws of physics. And, on this reading, he goes on to offer others, in support of this belief, the obvious argument that these laws work, in the unique, extraordinary way that they do. But one can agree with him about this last part without buying into his metaphysics.
Or can one? Is this really all there is to Weinbergs queer talk of the laws being real? I am not so sure. It continues as follows:
Sarah Franklin (in an article in the same issue of Social Text as Sokals hoax) challenges an argument of Richard Dawkins, that in relying on the working of airplanes we show our acceptance of the working of the laws of nature, remarking that some airlines show prayer films during take-off to invoke the aid of Allah to remain safely airborne. Does Franklin think that Dawkins argument does not apply to her? If so, would she be willing to give up the use of the laws of physics in designing aircraft, and rely on prayers instead?
But even if Franklin should happen to believe that Dawkins claim applies to her, this has no bearing on whether there are people to whom it does not apply.19 Why then does Weinberg respond to her suggestion that there are by challenging Franklin about her beliefs? Is this merely a logical lapse? I see no way of telling. More important, in his challenge to Franklin, Weinberg seems to confuse ignorance with indifference. Take my own case. I would be lying if I said that Dawkins remark applies to me because I know nearly nothing about how airplanes are constructed. But it doesnt follow that I dont care or that I believe that any way of constructing them is as good as any other.
Weinberg
seems to lose sight of the important fact that we can trust science
and even be in awe of it without knowing many of its laws, much less
feeling a need to formulate metaphysical views about how real
they are. How could formulating such views make a difference to us?
Werners wanderings
Weinberg finds Heisenbergs remark dreadful. But, because he doesnt give any reason for this opinion, for all we know, he has none. Actually, we don't even know what Weinberg thinks Heisenberg means by the remarkin particular, by saying that science sees itself as an actor. I dont think I know what this means. Why should I assume that Weinberg does? Then there is the parenthetical ad hominum,20 in which the innocent-looking expression not always masks the looniness of linking Heisenbergs metaphysical remark to his allegedly careless (rather than deliberate) mistakes in certain wartime calculations in applied physics. Perhaps it is just carelessness, but Weinberg writes as if he would have us believe that some people can always be counted on to think carefully and, also, that if anybody (Heisenberg, Weinberg, Stolzenberg, it doesnt matter who) once in his life failed to think carefully, this is evidence that he is the kind of person who is likely to do it again. 21 This is what I mean by the looniness.
To put it simply
To put it simply [Sokals] targets often take positions that seem to me (and I gather to Sokal) to make no sense of there is an objective reality. To put it simply, if scientists are talking about something real, then what they say is true or false. If it is true, then how can it depend on the social context of the scientist? If it is false, how can it help to liberate us?
Even if there is an objective reality, it does not follow that scientists are talking about it, no matter how much they may hope they are. Secondly, one crucial way in which the truth of a scientific statement depends on the social context of the scientist is that it depends upon the meaning of the statement, which in turn is a never finished product of that social context. 22 Finally, to see how a false statement can help to liberate us, it suffices to note that a false belief sometimes has a favorable outcome. (E.g., because you were mistaken about the time of departure, you missed a flight that crashed.)
Weinberg reads Harding
I quoted [Sandra Harding] as calling modern science (and especially physics) not only sexist but also racist, classist, and culturally coercive, and arguing that Physics and chemistry, mathematics and logic, bear the fingerprints of their distinctive cultural creators no less than do anthropology and history. It seemed to me that this statement could make sense only to a relativist; what is the good of wishing that the conclusions of scientific work were friendlier to multicultural or feminist concerns if these conclusions are to be an accurate account of objective reality? 23
What do Hardings remarks have to do with relativism? They are empirical claims, or would be if they were made more precise. How did Weinberg miss this? If he wishes to challenge these remarks, he should be looking at Hardings evidence and arguments. Also, where does he see her wishing for anything? could make sense only to a relativist, she says:
Lynch corrects Weinberg
[If] we ever discover intelligent creatures on some distant planet and translate their scientific works, we will find that we and they have discovered the same laws.
Why should this be so? Weinberg seems to consider it obvious, which it surely is not. After repeating it in his opening statement in The One Culture: A Conversation about Science, he acknowledges in the third (238-239)that this is not what he should have said:
In his essay in this book, Michael Lynch very properly caught me up on this and pointed out that the scientific works of intelligent creatures who inhabited Earth until a few centuries ago did not resemble the theories we believe in today.24
Clues to the past?
Some historians do not deny the reality of the laws of nature, but nevertheless refuse to take present scientific knowledge into account in describing the science work of the past. This is partly to avoid anachronisms, like supposing that scientists of the past ought to have seen things in the way we do . The problem is that if we try to avoid this sort of anachronism by ignoring present scientific knowledge, we give up clues to the past that cannot be obtained in any other way. (Sokals hoax)
This is an intriguing claim. Clues to the past that cannot be obtained in any other way. I dont doubt that some version of this claim is true 25 . But here my concern is only with Weinbergs attempt to make good on it. Here is the example he offers.
In the late 1890s, J. J. Thomson carried out a celebrated series of measurements of the ratio of the electrons mass and charge, and though the values he found were spread over a wide range, he persistently emphasized measurements that gave results at the high end of the range. The historical record alone would not allow us to decide whether this was because these results tended to confirm his first measurement, or because they were actually more careful measurements. Why not use the clue that the second alternative is unlikely because the large value that was favored by Thomson is almost twice what we know today as the correct value?
Weinberg seems to expect us to accept that he somehow knows that these two alternativesthe first of which is pulled out of a hat and the second is an explanation only in the syntactic sense that the word because precedes the alleged explanation and follows a description of the phenomenon to be explainedare the only ones that we need to consider. But why should we take word for this implausible claim? More important, even if the higher measurements had been actually more careful, how could this have helped make Thomson favor them (whatever this means) unless he believed that they were more careful? 26 But he might have believed this even if these measurements were not actually more careful. 27 And we can delete might because Thomson makes it clear in his article that he suspected that the experiments that yielded the higher values were more careful. 28
Rationality and witchcraft
As I mentioned earlier, our civilization has been powerfully affected by the discovery that nature is strictly governed by impersonal laws. As an example, I like to quote the remark of Hugh Trevor-Roper, that one of the early effects of this discovery was to reduce the enthusiasm for burning witches.
According to Stuart Clark, author of Thinking with Demons: the idea of witchcraft in early modern Europe (Oxford 1997), a more thorough investigation reveals a very different story. Enthusiasm for burning witches did wane during the seventeenth century but the discovery that nature is strictly governed by impersonal laws seems to have had little to do with it. By contrast, religious and legal considerations loomed large. Weinberg might have done better to claim that the acceptance of a mechanical theory of nature eventually contributed to the adoption of a new worldview, not only of nature, in which there was no longer a significant role for witchcraft. But this took time and before such a worldview took hold, witchcraft was a respectable subject of scientific inquiry. For example, on page 297, Clark writes:
But the most illustrious of Glanvills collaborators in witchcraft research was Robert Boyle, likewise a leading founder of the Royal Society. He and Glanvill corresponded on the question of the reality of witchcraft, with Boyle encouraging Glanvill to think of it as a proper subject for science. As the one fully corroborated and verified account of demonic activity that would clinch the matter, Boyle chose the story of the devil of Mâcon in France, originally compiled by François Perrault.
And on page 306, we find:
As late as 1737, William Whiston, Newton's disciple and his successor in the Lucasian chair of mathematics, wrote that the assaults of invisible demons, as long as they were well attested, were 'no more to be denied, because we cannot, at present, give a direct solution of them, than are Mr. Boyle's experiments about the elasticity of the air; or Sir Isaac Newton's demonstrations about the power of gravity, are to be denied, because neither of them are to be solved by mechanical causes.'29
Weinberg concludes:
We will need to confirm and strengthen the vision of a rationally understandable world to guard us from the irrationalities that still beset humanity.
Finally, the last sentence of Weinbergs remark, 30 together with the preceding one, suggests that he believes that, in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, witch burning was irrational. But because he makes no attempt to justify this, for all we know, it is merely an irrational prejudice. Nor does he attempt to explain how confirming and strengthening his vision of a rationally understandable world will guard us from the irrationalities that still beset humanity. Indeed, except for his ill-considered choice of witch burning, Weinberg gives us no sense of what, in his view, are the irrationalities that still beset humanity. But isn't one of them holding so fast to a vision-for example, to that of a rationally understandable universethat one is unable to understand other points of view? If Weinberg disagrees, he needs to explain why. And if he agrees, he needs to explain how holding fast to his own vision of a rationally understandable universe guards him from holding so fast to it that he is unable to understand other points of view. 31
1 Updated March 15, 2004
2 The oracle of deconstruction (42), Now you believe it (54), The correct answer, take one (55).
3 Mystery Science Theater by Social Text editors, Bruce Robbins and Andrew Ross, Lingua Franca July/August, 1996.
4 E.g., blackmail or a threat of being shunned.
5 According to Weinberg, much of Sokals account of developments in physics was quite accurate but it was heavily adulterated with howlers, most of which would have been detected by any undergraduate physics major.
6 Words have meanings but I defy the reader to interpret Sokals statement as being about words or other signs.
7 If it is not unique, how can he fault the editors of Social Text for not adopting it?
8 Furthermore, before mathematics was rigorized in the late nineteenth century, whatever mathematical objects were thought to be, they were not sets!
9 Sokal seemed resistant to any revisions, and indeed insisted on retaining almost all of his footnotes and bibliographic apparatus on the grounds that his peers, in science, expected extensive documentation of this sort. (Italics added) Editors Bruce Robbins and Andrew Ross, Mystery Science Theater, Lingua Franca, July/August 1996.)
10 By ignoring the first reading, Weinberg missed the opportunity to criticize the editors for tolerating this choice example of postmodernist obfuscation.
11 When my mathematician wife heard me utter the words, complex number theory, she immediately replied, There is no such thing.
12 One colleague who heard me say complex number theory confessed later that he thought I had said, complex function theory.
13 The preceding example also is of this type. In it, Sokal gives his sly mock approval of Markleys mistake by mimicking it.
14 Einsteins solution is a solution within relativity theory.
15 I suspect that one reason Latours talk of a third actor was misunderstood is that, whereas physicists tend to fixate on the point that we do not need to use a third frame to make the comparison, Latour fixates instead on the point that we are not forced to use one of the first two.
16 On my forgiving reading, Latour is saying roughly: Suppose the man on the train can plot his observations of a falling stone (or any other event) and transmit the graph to the man on the embankment, who transforms it into his embankment coordinates. If he finds that it agrees with his own graph of a falling stone (or any other event he observed), he concludes that they observed the same event.
17 For proof that this is indeed the quotation, see p. 231 of Fashionable Nonsense and then pp. 228-32.
18 How likely is it that she would mention the problem of borders right after mentioning fuzzy sets and not mean that problem of borders? At the very least, Weinberg has no warrant to dismiss this reading.
19 If the Pope were to remark that not everyone is Catholic, would it make sense to reply by asking whether the Pope believes that he is not Catholic?
20 The bit after the but.
21 And, therefore, cannot be counted on to think carefully.
22See Wittgenstein on rule-following in his Philosophical Investigations.
23 Weinberg goes on to say that Harding denied that she is a relativist and he did not press the matter.
24 In what he goes on to say, Weinberg makes it fairly clear that he meant to talk only about aliens whose scientific work has reached what he calls the asymptotic limit.
25 But cannot seems too strong.
26 The lower measurements might well have been actually more careful, they are close to the true value, yet Thomson did not favor them. Why then does Weinberg take seriously the possibility (if only to rule it out) that Thomson would have done so if it had been the higher measurement?
27 E.g., there might have been an undetected systematic error.
28 For more about this alleged clue to the past, see Kinder, gentler science wars in Social Studies of Science, February, 2004.
29 There is a great deal more about these and related matters in Clarks opus, especially in Science (151-311), which includes such chapters as Witchcraft and science, The devil in nature, The causes of witchcraft, Believers and sceptics, Natural magic, Demonic magic and Witchcraft and the Scientific Revolution.
30 Which is also the last sentence of his essay.
31 I don't think it does.